http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cya.2016.01.008
Paper Research
Corruption as an organizational process: Understanding
the logic of the denormalization of corruption
Corrupción como
proceso organizacional: comprendiendo la lógica de la desnormalización
de la corrupción
David Arellano Gault
Centro de
Investigación y Docencia Económicas, México
email: david.arellano@cide.edu
Abstract
This
article discusses the basic assumptions of an individualist vision on
corruption. A different argument based on “social density” of the phenomenon is
proposed instead: the process of normalization of corruption. Under this
umbrella, corruption is a political concept that looks to impose a particular
vision on what are “right” behaviors based on a sharp and unrealistic
separation of the public and private sphere. A review of the organizational
literature on corruption is developed, with the aim of understanding how
organizational processes of socialization triggers behaviors that make corrupt
acts to appear as “normal” under the organizational logic. Persons find
themselves in a “slippery slope”, generating agreements and social dynamics
that are able to produce corrupt logics under the normal life of an
organization. A plea for discussing the social processes needed to
“un-normalize” corruption is defended a conceptualization that goes beyond an
individualist and moralist vision of the phenomenon.
Keywords: Corruption, Organizational corruption, Socialization,
Rationalization, Strategies against corruption.
JEL classification: M48, K42, Z13.
Resumen
El artículo cuestiona los supuestos de la
visión individualista de la corrupción y se introduce al contrario una
conceptualización más «densa socialmente»: el proceso de normalización de la
corrupción. En esta última lógica, se advierte que una definición de corrupción
es siempre una definición política e ideológica que intenta imponer una visión
determinada de comportamientos «adecuados» de acuerdo a una separación
pretendidamente tajante y clara entre las esferas de lo público y lo privado.
Se realiza una revisión de parte de la literatura sobre corrupción
organizacional, con el fin de comprender cómo las rutinas, procesos y
estructuras de socialización propias de la arena organizacional pueden llevar
justamente a las personas a «caer en resbaladilla»
hacia una dinámica de corrupción. A normalizarla en otras palabras. Se concluye
con un llamado a discutir los procesos de desnormalización
de la corrupción, como estrategia sustantiva más allá de la visión
individualista o moralista del fenómeno.
Palabras clave: Corrupción, Corrupción organizacional,
Socialización, Racionalización,
Estrategias
contra la corrupción.
Códigos JEL: M48, K42, Z13.
Received: 07/04/2015
Accepted: 14/01/2016
Introduction
It is common, in the
literature on corruption (e.g., Nye,
1967; Rose-Ackerman, 1978 ) to define it as an act of an individual, an
inappropriate or deviated act according to certain parameters or social values that
are relatively accepted in a society or group. This definition even opens the
possibility to understand that, beyond the inappropriateness of the behavior of
the person, it could be considered, under certain circumstances, as a rational
or calculated behavior. In other words, corruption, from this analytical angle,
is the decision made by an individual during a transaction with another
individual or group of individuals, (unduly) taking advantage of from a
specific position in this relation or
transaction. This individualistic vision is sustained on a starting point: that
the individual knows or understands in a broad manner, the situation in which
she is and has calculated that behaving corruptly is convenient or beneficial
to her. This way, a very particular interaction model is formed between actors
that consciously calculate and act, measuring the consequences with a certain
logic and intention. In this way, when placing emphasis in calculating
individuals that act substantively thanks to this calculation ability (i.e.,
based on a conscious behavior), corruption is seen as a decision made by
individuals under a certain and particular value context. In this logic of
conscious and calculating individuals we can infer several things: first, that
corruption is inevitable in social relations, as it is funded in the
calculations of rational actors. Second, fighting it is basically a matter of
affecting the balance between cost and benefit that the individuals are able to
calculate.
The
main issue to be considered in this article is that this individualistic vision
is incredibly limited, first, to understand the phenomenon in its entirety and
therefore, as a second point, to propose long-term solutions. The main
objective of this document is to demonstrate, through a review of the
literature on organizational corruption, that corruption is not a phenomenon
where individuals enter discreet relations, but rather a dense social
phenomenon. It is a social relation, in other words. And this social logic is
both true for corruption in the private sector as it is in the public one, thus
this article does not make a particular distinction between them. In other
words, we speak of corruption in organizations of any type. From the review of
this organizational literature of corruption we seek to fairly identify how
corruption may be normalized as a social process with stages and socialization
processes and rationalization.
The way
in which the argument is developed is by analyzing how the studies of
organizational corruption place significant emphasis in the group and social
space where the decision is made and where the behavior generates. In this
manner, we arrive to very different diagnoses and conclusions, which a lot of
the time are counterintuitive with regard to the individualistic vision. The
point of departure is therefore that corruption is generated and thrives in the
world of social relations, where the individuals, their agency, their behavior,
are closely linked and affected by the interactions and context where they play
and build their own image, their own will ( de
Graff, 2007 ). The behavior is a product that is rational, emotional and relational
( Chugh, Bazerman,
& Banaji, 2005 , p. 79), where the
interactions and rules and structures within which the people behave do matter.
In this article, we will follow the perspective of Chibnall
and Saunders where corruption is seen as a “negotiated classification of a
behavior before an inherent quality on the behavior itself” (1977, p. 139). In
other words, the concept of corruption is a very particular social construct of
a society that, in its imaginary standards, has tried to separate the private
from the public in the clearest and strictest way possible. Only this way is it
feasible to find definitions that establish that corruption is, for example,
the abuse of an organizational position to illegitimately gain benefits ( Ananad et al., 2004 , p. 40). This classic
definition implicitly speaks of a clear differentiation of the private benefit
over the collective or group benefit; it is a permanent essence of the
different contemporary definitions of corruption.1
To discuss the huge
social and normative burden that the classic definitions of corruption have,
the following is important. Stating that corruption is a wrongful act, requires
to define the following: for whom is it wrongful? In what context A vision
based on the idea of “wrongful” implies that there is an external, clear, legit
parameter that surrounds an individual and a group, which clearly marks with
relative clarity what makes a behavior correct or corrupt. Even if this does
sound reasonable and easy to understand, it is not really so in practice. For
example, if the definition is so clear on what is wrongful then it should be
clear on the contrary as well: how can you define a no-corruption state? ( Philp, 1997 ). To answer such question is no
easy task, therefore, we’ve tried to form definitions that are not of the
corruption phenomenon as it is, but of some of its characteristics. People have
attempted to generate clear distinctions on what acts of legitimate benefit
means, for example (using political strategies to rise to higher levels in the
organization in order to earn more money and prestige is legitimate, but
helping a relative into the organization is not). A person can suspect being in
a conflict of interest; for example, if they had a friend for several years and
now, in a new position, it could negatively affect their judgment. Socially
speaking, conceptual negotiation would imply that the person evaluates these
possibilities in at least three complex steps: first, if the friendship has the
power to influence, second, if said influence could clearly be illegitimate or
only improper (to the eyes of certain actors), and third, define what the
consequences of such influence could be. Each step implies a profound
reflection and understanding of the context of the situation on behalf of the
actor. This makes it possible to propose that all definitions of corruption
are, in essence, fighting to negotiate a classification of behaviors,
suspecting that that classification explains the nature of the phenomenon.
In the
same manner, a corrupt group or organizational context could be implemented
before the arrival of a certain person to the organization. The corrupt social
relation could be installed so it has become normalized ( Bratsis, 2003 , p. 17), it could even
be an instituted rule for the integration of the group. In the case of
organizations therefore, a corrupt act may be seen as corruption by an external
group under certain parameters, but those within may think the same act as a
normal or non-corrupt act.
The
person is embedded in social spaces
such as the organizations, and in this sense, the group logic imposes a series
of possibilities and conditions on the way people handle and present themselves
in such social spaces. There is, for instance, important literature on the
anthropologic, cultural and discursive logic of corruption ( Andersson & Heywood, 2009; Graaf, Wagenaar and Hoenderboom, 2010 , p. 99; Haller and Shore, 2005; Sissaner,
2001 ). The secrecy in an organization, for instance, has to do with the
conventions that regulate certain groups, who knows what, what information they
possess and why ( Costas and Grey, 2014 , p. 10). The rules and
the norms, formal and informal, of the group or groups, establish this
“normality” of relations that could only be seen as “strange” under the light
of an external code of reference that establishes that this secrecy could be a
source of corruption. The social density of the corruption brings to the front
the analysis of arguments, even counterintuitive ones, such as those that state
that the people accused of corruption could argue that they did not know that
what they were doing was wrong.
This
article has a specific method: perform a review of the organizational
literature on corruption which is little-known in the field of debate on this
topic. This method has the advantage of introducing a series of concepts and
discussions that have been debated very little in the dominant debate spaces on
corruption, more prone to normative and instrumental debates. This chosen
method has, however, some disadvantages: the main one being the lack of
specific empirical studies. We have developed some of these studies in other places
( Arellano, 2012 ). However, we hope
that this article boosts the interest in making more empirical studies,
especially for the case of corruption in Mexico and Latin America.
That said,
from the review of the literature on organizational corruption, the article
establishes that it is necessary, if we want to fight corruption in an
organization or group of organizations, to relativize the strategies that see
it as a problem of individuals calculating costs and benefits. Seen as a dense
social phenomenon, a product of social relations, corruption is a point of
arrival and not of departure. For an actor with this logic, to classify and
understand a specific act, and to be able to differentiate it as an honest or
dishonest act implies that the person would have to compare it against the
agreements and practices established, as a group, as normal in their daily
practice. Denormalizing
corruption seems to be the center of a strategy that completely understands
this collective construction of the phenomenon and of the acts that comprise
it.
The
article comprises five sections including this introduction. In Section 2 we
discuss the organization as a social process that forms behaviors in a web of
rules, senses and norms that generate the organizational “normality”. This
normality built in the space where, in the search to make sense of people's
behavior, the organizations create social interaction processes that attempt to
socialize people in their dynamics, including those that could be considered as
corrupt (Section 3). Sure enough, it may seem counterintuitive but the
socialization process also works for events such as corruption, where people
rationalize their acts by giving them a sense within an organizational scheme.
This rationalization allows people to reduce their cognitive dissonance,
meaning, the sense of angst before the probability of doing a wrongful act
(through certain internal or external patterns to the organization). In the fourth
section we explain how these rationalization and socialization processes can
therefore constitute a stable dynamic in time, one that builds a certain plot
of relations that reinforce each other, establishing a species of “slide” where
more and more people, more frequently fall or are trapped in corrupt networks.
They are not rationalized and become a part of the organizational scheme as
normal behavior, but they also become generalized. And in that moment it is
possible to speak of an organization that has turned corruption into a normal
and justified act (it has normalized acts that seen in other contexts or by
other actors can be classified as corrupt acts). In the last section we present
some conclusions regarding the impact that the argument of corruption
normalization can have on the strategies to fight this phenomenon that is a
focus of attention and concern among society.
Organizations with corrupt individuals or corrupt organizations?
The reasons why an individual carries out
dishonest actions are several and diverse. Corruption is in fact a social
phenomenon: an individual chooses to be corrupt or carries out a dishonest
action (we will see that there is a difference between the two) always in a
context where their psychological relations, experiences, values and the social
interactions that they live and constantly suffer, become a part of the
equation ( Rest, 1986).
Berger and Luckmann (1978) are very clear regarding how every human interaction
starts, becomes and is defined within a social logic: interactions create bonds
between people. Bonds that can last a second or decades. Bonds that are capable
of eventually creating groups and sub-groups that share objectives or beliefs.
These bonds can also be seen as socialization dynamics, meaning,
self-organization dynamics ( Goffman,
1983 ):
once bonds have been created, they tend to become more stable and are able to
reproduce to other people as they communicate and share, e.g., through
routines. In this context, socialization implies the creation and re-creation
of perceptions and eventually behaviors that the individuals induce, understand
and generate in order to take the relationship between them to a (or several)
different context, according to the perspective of each agent involved.
The socialization process, being
situational and contingent at the core (depending on the specific persons and
situations in which they are) comprises stabilizing elements, but that are
ultimately changing and modifiable. Due to this, socialization mechanisms may
be contradictory, obscure, and counterintuitive. Agency and structure ( Giddens,
1984 , p.
5) are merely interpreted, thus there is no guarantee that the socialization
processes are able to escape the interaction dynamics. In other words,
socialization processes can generate several different reactions from the
different agents and they can also create unexpected effects that could be counterintuitive
for the actors involved. This is what usually happens in those organizations
that fall for the logic of corruption: they have socialized practices and
behaviors that induce people to corruption, a lot of the time as an unexpected
and undesired consequence.
Following this line of thought, we can
understand how in a specific organizational framework, the definition of what a
dishonest behavior is, is linked to a classification and structure within what
is organizationally defined: a behavior is classified by some and in certain circumstances as such because it violates certain
organizational (or group) standards that are generally accepted (all of this
does not necessarily mean that this agreement is unanimous or that it is the
same for everyone; Kish-Gephart, Harrison,
& Treviño, 2010 , p. 2).2 The cases being
discussed are therefore multiplied: people that defend what they did not know
were corrupt acts, acts that in a particular context are defined as corrupt and
in another are not, acts that are temporarily seen as acceptable but that given
certain circumstances stop being so.
It is important to study and understand
how sense and socialization are organizationally formed, especially if we are
discussing the normalization of acts such as corruption. We can start by
establishing that the organizations can be seen as social creatures comprised
by people who behave a certain way ( Simon,
Thompson, & Smithburg, 2010 [1950] : 55). This behavior is based on the
combination of the burdens and individual situations of each participant and on
the relationships that the person has with other people, in a framework with a
level of formality and a certain degree of domination that pretends to unite
these relationships with a particular aim, and in a framework that comprises a
degree of “normality” and what is “acceptable”. At any rate, in the organized
framework, people socialize their thoughts and intentions within a not so rigid
framework but that does comprise behaviors aimed to a certain objective and
with certain premises. This is why people comprise organizations, but
organizations are more than just the people that comprise them: they become a
series of relations between people, social, group and individual bonds,
incidental but that become stable over time.
In this manner, when speaking of
corruption, it is almost impossible not to speak of organization. Corrupter and
corrupted, corrupt people and victims, they are sooner or later found within
the framework of the organizations that regulate, monitor, encourage or attempt
to control them. Therefore, trying to understand how corruption is generated is
to attempt to understand the dynamic of the bonds and relationships (temporal
or semi-permanent) that are built between the different agents so that this
practice is possible to be carried out and even to stabilize (as the systemic
corruption idea insinuates).
When introducing the organizational
variable, the psychological and group elements of corruption appear with
clarity and without any moralistic tones. This in the tradition of Goffman who
tried to “read” the presentation processes between people, such as the logical
acts, including the machination and settling of the façade used to present themselves
in a group reunion within the organization. For example, the hiding and deceit
process that tends to lead organizations to systematize corruption acts is not
generated in one act alone, but it develops from a non-detected lie to bigger
lies to support the original lie ( Messick & Bazerman,
1996 , p.
21). It is hard for a lie or a deceitful action to be an individual activity in
an organization: deceitful actions involve more and more people little by
little: coworkers and even authorities could start to put pressure in order to
maintain the network of lies ( Cialdini, Pterova,
& Goldstein, 2004 , p. 70–71). The language can change, the
organizational agents change the words to avoid making them seem like lies or
questionable facts, rather to make them more “hygienic” (e.g. instead of
speaking about bribery use phrases like “grease the machinery”, Bandura,
1990 ).
These elements, in the end, give evidence on how the lies and deceit can begin
in a reduced dimension, grow and then get tangled in the network of personal
and hierarchical relations, falling, little by little, as if on a slide, in
social and institutional corrupt dynamics.
Two metaphors have tried to simplify these
organizational explanations (unfortunately, sometimes this is done with a
moralistic tone): the phenomenon of the “bad apple” or the “bad barrel”. One
person or a group of people who have decided to be corrupt and ethically
violate the organizational rules, become(s) the bad apple. In the case of the
bad barrel, we allude to the organization (or one of its structures or parts)
that has fallen in a corrupt dynamic that can be hidden in an aura of ethical
or rational action. Otherwise explained, corruption vs the organization, or
corruption in the name of the organization ( Pinto,
Leana, & Pil, 2008 , p. 685). The issue in every case seems
to be that, beyond labels, it is important to understand how a person can become
a bad apple, sometimes even without realizing it, and how in this process, the
barrel and its dynamic, could be of great importance for such effect. In the
following section we will introduce the organizational process of corruption as
it has been presented in the previous paragraphs.
The organizational processes of
corruption: normalized through rationalization and socialization
The most counterintuitive organizational
characteristic of corruption in organizations is that the acts of corruption
become normal . The literature in this regard is full of
evidence and references that indicate that, in general, the people that have
been processed for corruption deny having done something illegal or amoral ( Benson, 1985; Conklin, 1977; Cressey, 1986; Geis and Meier,
1979; Sykes & Matza, 1957 ).
One of the possible explanations for this
pretend paradox can be found, precisely, in the ability of organizations to routinize and
normalize the different activities, values and objectives of the individuals
and of the groups that comprise them. The same way an organization normalizes
the respect for hierarchy or the acceptable procedures in daily work, these
same dynamics seem to work to convert behavior that could be classified as
corrupt, into “normal” behavior. Furthermore, a group of non-corrupt behaviors
could combine with others that are corrupt, and an individual in particular may
not have the whole picture of the interaction between different agents. The
people in the organizations need to find the sense of what they do and their
perspective is always limited (by time, resources, skill, as the classic
concept of limited rationality of Simon,
1947 dictates). Thus, an organization builds a series of influence
mechanisms, routines and principles that help the members of the organization
make sense of their actions, saving time through routines, promoting
cooperation through standardized, specialized and compartmentalized processes.
All these, among other mechanisms or influence instruments. It is these same
mechanisms which, intentionally or not, are able to build normalization schemes
for action networks and corrupt behaviors.
From this starting point, the
organizational action is a social construct a la Berger and Luckmann (1978)
: the organizational actors form different interpretations and loyalties to
internalize different socialization logics. The group, the sub-group, the
department, the organization as a whole, the industry where the organization
thrives, and lastly, the country, the society, are different levels where the
actor internalizes and socializes the standards, the rules, the expectations,
and even the moral principles, which become a part in that collectivity ( Chibnall & Sauders, 1977
, p: 141). Evidently, this secondary socialization as is called by Berger and Luckmann, implies a process that can be contradictory in
its interpretation at different levels of aggregation. In short, the
socialization logics of one of the layers (e.g., the organization) could clash
against another level (e.g., the group). To accuse a colleague of corruption,
for example, could be what is more beneficial to the organization as a whole,
but morally, it could be seen by the group as an act of disloyalty. To disguise
some financial figures could be beneficial for the organization, under the
argument that good people made a mistake with good intentions, for example, but
it could be seen as an act of corruption at a societal level. How do human
beings deal with these fundamental contradictions? A possible answer is just
that, through rationalization.
Rationalization is an act of fundamental
interpretation and it is crucial so that an actor is able to become a social
actor. At least through Goffman
(1981) it is well understood that individuals know how to present
themselves before others with a fundamental strategy of successes and step
backs that allow them to build a certain image and provide an amount of
uncertainty to the expected interactions with others. Why obey a boss? Because
the legitimacy or hierarchy is believed, as per Weber. It is a necessary
rationalization for the formation of the social interaction network. This rationalization
does not stop being an interpretation, a strategy to provide sense, a patchwork
of essence and appearance that the actors wish to be observed and at the same
time hope to remain hidden (opacity is a fundamental ingredient of interaction.
Arellano, 2010; Costas and Grey,
2014 ). Not only opacity, but also the secret and secrecy comprise a
fundamental part of the repertoire of interaction and communication strategies
in organizations ( Zerubavel, 2006
). When speaking of corruption, for example, the actors in a group within the
organization could have already created a rationalization that helps build this
act, not as a corrupt act, but as an accident or unnecessary act to achieve a
greater good, with the intention of maintaining a certain level of collective
moral health that justifies the group ( Ashforth & Anand, 2003, p. 16).
The range of rationalization options in
cases of corruption is diverse and broad. Let us summarize what the literature
on this topic has found in different experiences and cases ( Ananad et al., 2004, Ashforth & Ananad, 2003; Ashforth, Gioia, Robinson, & Treviño, 2008; Felps, Mitchell,
& Byington, 2006 , Fleming & Zyglidopoulos,
2009, Kish-Gephart et al., 2010; Pinto et al., 2008; Zyglidopoulos & Fleming, 2008; Zyglidopoulos,
Fleming, & Rothenberg, 2009 ).
Rejection of responsibility
This is the classic displacement that a
person can make to establish that they were part of a great machine where they
did not have the possibility of understanding that fraud or an act of
corruption was taking place. Or argue that they were only following orders or
that they were doing what everybody else was doing and therefore, it was a
moral act. In any case, it is rationalized that the person had no control over
the situation. A transit police officer that is immediately introduced by their
superiors and colleagues to the bribery fees to be paid each week, could show
signs of this type of normalization.
Damage denial
The agents that find themselves in these
circumstances can argue that in reality the acts for which they are being
accuse are of so little importance, compared, for example, with the earnings or
benefits of the organization, that it is not reasonable to say that it was
theft or an act of corruption. “Pilferage” or the over the counter request of
payment “for refreshments” can serve as an example.
Victim denial
A classic version of this rationalization
is to suggest that the receptor of the illegal or dishonest act is even more
dishonest, making them deserving of said treatment. That is to say, someone was
affected but said person is not a victim, but rather an instance so corrupt or
so grand and powerful and unjust, that the act classified as corruption was in
fact almost an act of vindication in the face of the injustices. The theft of
resources from a union to a large organization that refuses to pay better
salaries to its employees can serve as an example of this rationalization.
Social compensation
This rationalization is strong socially
speaking, but common: it implies giving importance or a relative value to the
beliefs or needs of others. If there are corrupt and powerful actors, and the
laws are considered unjust, then it is rationalized that they can be justified
in acting in an apparently dishonest manner, given that in reality “the others”
are the ones truly corrupt. Or when it is justified that a corrupt act in
reality reduces great prejudices toward weak persons (this small bribe prevents
worse consequences for a relatively defenseless person). Many of the “small” bribes
can follow this logic: the bribe at least helps so others pay less and even
prevent that the payment reaches the “truly corrupt”.
Higher loyalties
The different layers of socialization that
individuals live lead to contradictions between loyalties to different groups.
The esprit de corps can be stronger than loyalties to “greater” logics such as
the law or standards. It is a rather contradictory rationalization, but very
real: the law is corrupted in the name of justice, making the ends justify the
means. A police officer can refuse to accuse another due to this esprit de
corps, or use dishonest influences in order to force a guilty verdict in the
conviction of an accused.
The metaphor of balance
This rationalization implies the
calculation that can be carried out from the “contributions” of a person that
considers them so large that they “deserve” a particular retribution (which
sometimes said person has taken illegally). In other words, a bureaucrat can
argue that they work many hours, many more than the others, and therefore the
pilferage or bribe they requested was justified as compensation in the face of
the extra effort given.
Evidently, these rationalizations can be
interpreted as simple lies or hypocritical justifications. However, the story
is not that simple. Many times, these rationalizations are real interpretation
and justification mechanisms, which allow the actor to feel better about
themselves, reducing anguish or dissonance between their general values and
their particular actions ( Gigerenzer,
2002 ). Denial, in psychology, is not exclusively an act of
hypocrisy, but rather a mental and social process of justification and
modification of the interpretation parameters on the part of human beings ( Bargh Tanya and Chartrand, 1999, p. 475; Lerner & Tetlock,
1999 , p. 263). Self-deception, as counterintuitive as it sounds, is
a fundamental reality, widely studied in psychology as an act of modification
of the mental parameters in order to evaluate reality ( Eagleman, 2012; Lehrer, 2009, Ainslie, 2001 ). In
other words, people build stories and perceptions in such a way to be able to
reduce and even eliminate (at least temporarily) the cognitive dissonance or
anguish that knowing that they are committing an unduly act produces ( Festinger, 1957 ). Said dissonance is an internal
tension of the ideas or emotions of the person with regard to what they observe
to be or could be reality. By reducing the dissonance, it is possible to feel
less morally affected, for example, in the face of an act carried out under
particular circumstances and in specific contexts. A person, thus, can reduce
cognitive dissonance if they rationalize that their act of corruption was not
so serious, was followed by others, was ordered by others, or if it is part of
an act of redistributive “justice” against the “true villains”. The main point
is that rationalization implies a real and creative effort with impacts
effective in the interpretation of the person regarding the honesty or lack
thereof of an act. Furthermore, this rationalization can be broadly reinforced
through the organization and its groups, in a systematic or implicit form of
routines or practices.
Corrupting the organization: socialization or the corruption
slippery-slope
The mental and relational process that
makes a corrupt act not be seen or rationalized as such by the people, can be
broadly reinforced by the organizational dynamic. Organizations are usually
seen as instruments or semi-robotic machines where the people are the gears of
a well-oiled machine. However, in reality, organizations are social constructs
assumed to be formalized, but which build intricate and intense human and
social relations in order to direct many people to reach agreements, form
groups, internalize behaviors and values, as well as satisfy the achievement of
objectives, people who must also interpret and give sense to said objectives ( Weick, 2001).
A person that enters an organization
begins a dense socialization process. What is the organization? What people
comprise it? What groups manage it? What are the prevailing values of
hierarchy, obedience, cooperation, conflict and negotiation?..among
many other processes that any person is required to decode when entering an
organization ( Kunda, 1992 ). These social forces and dynamics
that allow people to be introduced and to learn and build their role and
function within the organization, work for formalized matters (such as
identifying the hierarchy and the rules of communication), as do they for the
socialization of actions or behaviors that could, given time, feed corruption.
This contraction is one of the most important to understand, as it explains
rather clearly why the persons generally accused of corruption do not think
themselves guilty of said acts. In other words, we are not speaking only of
cynicism or of the calculation of people to deny corruption. Nor only of the
psychological process that allows for rationalization as analyzed in the
section above. We are also speaking of the very organizational processes that
allow a person to be part of the group, of the organization, which act and
function in order to place and position the actor in relational plots, and of
actors who, in the end, could be classified as corrupt. However, in this case,
we speak of acts of corruption which the very organizational processes,
paradoxically, helped to cement, consolidate and make them customary.
In this section we will review four
classic socialization process of corruption ( Milgram [1974] 2005): agentification , cooptation, incrementalism and
compromise. These four processes allow, in principle, to understand how the
social dynamic of introducing a person to the organizational logic comes about
gradually, as a true learning process of the interaction rules and standards in
a collective. The preferred metaphor is that of the “slippery-slope”: the way
the mental and social processes of rationalization are rebuilt and
strengthened, little by little, by the organizational logic of interaction. In
the case of corruption, the organizations can create conditions so that the
people gradually “slide” to commit acts of corruption in a process that
facilitates said acts to be rationalized and justified as “normal” or at least
acceptable from the logic of the group or even that of the organization. So
that this “slide” effect is generated, it is necessary for the person to be
incorporated into the rules and traditions or organizational practices, being
accepted as an integrated or embedded agent into said rules and practices
(further in this document we shall discuss this as agentification ). Thanks to this process, the person in
the organization continues to be the same individual who entered into it, but
at the same time they are a different person: the one who obeys, is accepted,
“knows” how to interpret and understands the “culture” or “nature” of the
organization as a sub-world where many of their behaviors and feelings only
have logic while they are within the organization.3
Organizational agentification
Agentification is the psychological and social process
that leads a person to internalize their role within the organization and to
observe it and its members with the legitimacy and authority to direct their
behavior. In a way it is one of the organizational keys in constructing the
other three socialization processes (cooptation, incrementalism, and
compromise).
The organizations can be seen as social
constructs that try to formalize diverse mechanisms of human interaction with
the purpose of achieving certain relatively specified (but never closed) ends.
The mechanisms of human interaction are constituted, at least in part, in an
intersubjective game of mutual expectations between the agents: someone
searches for something that in some manner depends on the reaction of another,
thus it intuits that it is required and it depends, in some manner, on the
reaction of another. This is the base of interaction that generates social
links, invisible but not any less real, which link the agents. These links of
human relation are played in various social spaces, many of them in face to
face relations ( Goffman, 1983
). They are links that force many times for an interaction to be illocutionary or
dramatized, dependent on their own mask games, secrets and lies (which have
been solidly studied in psychology since at least the classic text of Simmel, 1906 ). The
organizations, thus seen, constitute spaces that are intended formalized, thus
all these intertwined games exist and are maintained in but a facet that bases
their legitimacy in the formalization of the relations. The formal importance
is, therefore, not in that it displaces or eliminates “informal” or human face
to face or illocutionary logic: what the organization does, in any
case, is to give legitimacy to a formal facet such as organizer or strict floor
on which the informal game is played. An organization that is seen as legitimate
by the people is a strong source of obedience and, therefore, a strong means to
direct behaviors toward certain directions. The famous experiment by Milgram ([1974] 2005)
confirms how the weight of the authority triggers a series of reactions,
thoughts, assumptions and justifications that allow people to rationalize their
actions in light of the people and their authority and the rules or standards
defended in their name. The “agentic state” ( Milgram [1974], 2005 , p. 133) is that in
which the individual, who can consider themselves as autonomous in certain
circumstances, once inside the organization, transforms their behavior and
rational to the logic of the order of the organization. According to Milgran, they enter a state that allows for the obedience
of the person, something that is very well done by the organizations.
Thus, the agentic
organizational person is the person who “knows” how to behave in the
organization. To this end, in order to “know” and be accepted, they need to
behave in a certain way that many times implies behaviors that appear only
while within the organization. The point here is not to plant a dichotomy, as
Milgram has sometimes been critiqued of doing ( Darley, 2001 , p. 207), between the individual
as such outside the organization and “another person” who enters an agentic state : in
this case we refer, rather, to a series of social and organizational forces
that drive and direct the behavior of the people (once more, not as automata,
rather, as thinking people in an always moving social scheme).
Authority, obedience, accepted rules and
standards, standardization and routine, they are all organizational forces that
are capable of driving complex interpretations in people. Thus, the matter that
follows is that organizations are a highly important social force that
intrinsically, in a relatively normal manner, produce this type of agentic
state, which at the same time assures obedience and perseverance for the
achievement of objectives, and can, in certain circumstances, produce
systematized and standardized corruption.
Cooptation
One of the classic steps in which the
groups inside the organization induce changes on the people that enter the same
is by letting them know the benefits and powers that said person could have by
belonging to the formal group (and sometimes informal). Placing said benefits
and powers as part of the labor has been known in organizational literature as
“collateral payments” ( Cyert &
March, 1965 ). If said collateral payments come about from wrongful
activities, they can be introduced little by little as payments that action and
cooperation provide even if they are not formalized. It could even be that the
person recently introduced is not aware of the possible misappropriation of
resources until after some time and after having received said collateral
payments in a constant basis. The main point of cooptation is precisely to share
interests, earnings and risks. Once a person has been introduced to the red of
relations and benefits, it is more difficult for said person to comprehend the
implications of their participation in the organizational actions and
processes, even those that could be considered wrongful.
Incrementalism
Diverse studies on corruption in
organizations have noted that there is a gradual introduction process of the
people to the red of wrongful actions and decisions ( Van Gennep, 1960; McLean & Elkind, 2004 ). The process can begin by
assigning the newly arrived person small tasks, sometimes even insignificant,
but that allow them to introduce themselves into the chain of diverse actions
that lead to an organizational product or effect. This classic manner of
introducing a person to the organization and its processes can be used in turn
for wrongful effects. Once more, the person that in the beginning does not
understand the moral problematic of the effect of their action until they have
already participated in the chain, each time with more responsibilities and
probably with a position to now better understand the consequence of their
actions. It is also possible that this gradual introduction to the chain of
corruption makes it more difficult to leave it. The strength of the past, or of
past actions could then fall strongly on the person, making it difficult for
him to take the decision of not only leaving but also denouncing (or as it is
known in the literature, whistleblowing).
Compromise
The effective life of a person in an
organization is filled with moments in which they must face various types of
restrictions, regulatory obligations, and pressure to achieve objectives with
certain standards and do so in an organizational life of hierarchies,
horizontal relations with others, group links and even friendships or enmities.
It is not strange in these circumstances for one or more of these elements to
become contradictory. Achieving the objectives with efficiency could imply
dismissing people from other groups or from one's own group. Or perhaps
flexibly complying with certain rules or even disobeying them outright if it is
for the good of the group or the objectives of the organization. For example,
achieving results and standards tends to be one of the strongest pressures in
the contemporary organizational world. The insistence of taking the results as
the only thing that matters, in turbulent and uncertain contexts, impose on the
people a series of great pressures and anxieties in the face of the difficulty
and uncertainty of achieving said standards or indicators of results (see the
experimental studies of Lerner
& Tetlock, 1999 ). In this manner, an
individual can reach the point of accepting flexibilities in relations, rules
or processes with the purpose of meeting certain results or avoid certain
negative consequences. The commitment with the organization, with the group,
with the overall objectives, can be forces that make people begin to relax their
patterns of adherence to the standards or rules, first in a reduced manner, but
later gradually with greater flexibilities each time.
As can be quickly understood, the
rationalization and socialization dynamics reinforce each other mutually. When
the useful but extremely simple assumption of the individual calculating
decision-maker is ignored and both the mental and psychological mechanisms to
rationalize and give sense to one's own acts are understood, and they are then
introduced into an arena of relations, rules and organizational times,
corruption begins to be seen with a much more dynamic perspective. It is also
much more worrying as the difficulty that the mechanism that have looked to
deal with it have can be deduced.4
Conclusions
The objective of this article has been,
from a review of the literature on organizational corruption, to understand the
standardizing process of corruption. This process is one that is
counterintuitive and that can frustrate many people who would expect to find
quick and precise formulas to reduce the phenomenon (some even dream with
eliminating it completely). The organizational vision of corruption leaves it
clear that there is no such “silver bullet” and that corruption is a social
phenomenon of dense relations, where what is “normal” and “abnormal” is
negotiated and intersect in the arenas where the agents end up interacting on
the day to day.
A society and its organizations can
advance in reducing and limiting corruption. They require an interesting social
process: analyzing in-depth the practices, routines and rationalizations that
define their relations as normal. Understand, in other words, how the “normal”
logic in which the people relate in an organization can be generating that very
phenomenon of corruption.
The denormalization of corruption is thus a necessary and
extremely difficult step to carry out. It is difficult because it implies
delving into the social relations, into the processes that made routine a
series of behaviors that can even already be found rationalized.
One can begin understanding this denormalization if we accept that corruption is, after
all, a social category greatly loaded with values and expectations ( Rose-Ackerman,
2014 , p
4). The objective of this conclusion is not to discuss or to take a side, for
example, with regard to an argument that has been talked about recently (even
as extravagant, Caiden, Dwivedi, & Jabbra, 2001 , p 31): that corruption can be an inevitable
phenomenon and in some sense even a benefit in the long term socially speaking.
It is clear that, for many people, the
aforementioned statement has become important to act with regard to corruption
given its negative effects in many countries and contexts. The cases of
generalized corruption in governments such as that of Mexico, Brazil, Guatemala
(just to mention some that in this decade have gathered public attention) and
in companies such as Enron, Petrobras, and Parmalat which have garnered a great
deal of social attention as extremely worrying and grave cases. Without a
doubt, all of this pushes various analysts to propose solutions, preferably
quick and universal solutions. We can even already speak of an anti-corruption
community that has acquired its own political dynamic and logic. However, as we
have proposed here, the hope that corruption can be eliminated from the social
relations is not so simple to accomplish. It is even impossible, if we take to
the extreme the argument we have defended here. The organizational vision of
corruption is in fact a strong source in understanding why. The agent continues
to be the one that falls in a corrupt logic. However, the individual decision
can often be seen in social frameworks such as the organizations (as we have
discussed here), and to the individual calculating logic we then add the
emotional or motivational logic and the social or of the relations ( Chugh et al., 2005 , p. 78). Every one of these logics has
its own dynamic and the anti-corruption instruments that are considered and
implemented will be seen affected in a different manner by each of them. It is
probably because of this that the “battle” against corruption is so difficult
and produces variable results.
In any case, the acts of corruption are
many times a point of arrival more than a discrete decision of an individual
auto-controlled actor: the social interaction of people with emotions creates a
dynamic, a language, a timing of interaction and action, and a rationalization
that allows the actor to justify their action. The social space influences,
prepares, and normalizes the action and decisions. More importantly, it
normalizes the interpretation to make way for a series of actions which are
carried out almost automatically, making for certain acts to be normal. Normal
because others do them, normal because others justify them. Behaviors that
become normal because as a whole the responsibility has been distributed,
automatized, and organized. But perhaps more importantly, because by
normalizing, the organizational and social context demystifies social life as a
distant fairytale, with its good vs bad, with its paladins
vs monsters. The grays are much more interesting that the black and white
metaphor of the “fight of the pure against the corrupt”.5
Denormalizing corruption is thus part
of acting on the processes and routines that in practice are already
established in an organization, deconstructing
them in some form, with the purpose of understanding the casual social and
argumentative chains that support them. Understand corruption as a social
interaction makes it possible to study the rules of action, the group and
psychological elements that incite and procreate behaviors that end up
normalizing behaviors that derive into corruption.
Returning
to the task at hand, it is required to advance on three fronts of denormalization (under the condition of not losing
artificiality from sight): what individual characteristics lead to corruption?
What organizational processes are generated in order to normalize corrupt acts?
How are the processes and the organizational and institutional rules and
regulations reinforced to position corrupt individuals or to make individuals
become corrupt? In the moment that corruption is normalized, institutionalized,
and becomes systemic in an organization or in a group of organizations, these
three dimensions will be present recreating themselves.
References
Ackroyd, S., & Thompson, P. (1999). Organizational misbehaviour.
Londres: Sage.
http://dx.doi.org/10.4135/9781446222232
Ainslie, G. (2001). Break-down
of will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Anand, V., Ashforth,
B., Joshi, M., & Martini, P. (2004). Business as usual: The acceptance and
perpetuation of corruption in organizations. Academy of Management Executive,
18(2), 39–55.
Andersson, S., & Heywood, P.
(2009). The politics of perception: Use and abuse of transparency
international’s approach to measuring corruption. Political Studies, 57,
746–767. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2008.00758.x
Arellano, D. (2010). Reformas
administrativas y cambio organizacional: hacia el «efecto neto». Revista
Mexicana de Sociología, 2010(2), 225–254.
Arellano, D. (2012). ¿Podemos reducir la corrupción en México?
Límites y posibilidades de los instrumentos a nuestro alcance. México:
CIDE.
Ashforth, B., & Anand, V. (2003). The normalization of corruption in
organizations. Research in Organizational Behavior, 25, 1–52.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S0191-3085(03)25001-2
Ashforth, B., Gioia, D., Robinson, S., & Trevi
˜no, L. (2008). Re-viewing organizational corruption. Academy of Management
Review, 33(3), 670–684. http://dx.doi.org/10.5465/AMR.2008.32465714
Bandura, A. (1990).
Mechanisms of moral disengagement. In W. Reich (Ed.), Origins of terrorism:
Psychologies, ideologies, theologies, states of mind (pp. 161–191).
Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.
Bargh, J., & Chartrand, T. (1999). The
unbearable automaticity of being. American Psychologist, 54(7.),
462–479. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.54.7.462
Benson, M. (1985).
Denying the guilty mind: Accounting for involvement in a white-collar crime. Criminology, 23, 583–607.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-9125.1985.tb00365.x
Berger, P., & Luckman, T. (1978). La
construcción social de la realidad. Buenos Aires: Amorrortu.
Bratsis, F. P. (2003). The
construction of corruption, or rules of separation and illusions of purity in Burgeo is Societies. Social Text, 71(21–4)
http://dx.doi.org/10.1215/01642472-21-4 77-9, 9.33
Caiden, G., Dwivedi, O., & Jabbra, J.
(2001). Where corruption lives. Bloomfield: Kumarian
Press.
Chibnall, S., & Saunders, P.
(1977). Worlds apart: Notes on the social reality of corruption. The British
Journal of Sociology, 28(2), 138–154.
Chugh, D., Bazerman,
M., & Banaji, M. (2005). Bounded ethicality as a
psychological barrier to recognizing conflicts of interest. In D. Moore, D.
Moore, et al. (Eds.), Conflict of interest (pp. 74–95). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Cialdini, R. B., Pterova, P. K., & Goldstein, N. J. (2004). The hidden
costs of organizational dishonesty. Sloan Management Review, 45,
67–73.
Conklin, J. (1977). Business
crime in America. Englewood: Prentice-hall.
Costas, J., & Grey,
C. (2014). Bringing secrecy into de the open: Towards a theorization of the
social processes of organizational secrecy. Organization Studies, 35(10),
1423–1447. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0170840613515470
Cressey, D. (1986). Why
managers commit fraud. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Criminology,
19, 195–209.
Cyert, R., & March, J.
(1965). Teoría de las decisiones económicas de la empresa. México: Herrero.
Darley, J. (2001). The
dynamics of authority influences in organizations and the unintended action
consequences. In J. M. Darley, D. M. Messick, &
T. R. Tyler (Eds.), Social influences on ethical behavior in organizations (pp.
37–52). New Jersey: Erlbaum.
De Graaf,
G. (2007). Causes of corruption: Towards a contextual theory of corruption. Public
Administration Quarterly, 31(1-2), 39–86.
De Graaf,
G., Wagenaar, P., & Hoenderboom,
M. (2010). Constructing corruption. In G. de Graaf,
P. von Maravic, & P. Wagener (Eds.), The good
cause. Theoretical perspectives on corruption (pp. 98–114). Opladen & Famington Hills:
Barbara Budrich Pub.
Eagleman, D. (2012). Incognito.
The secrets lives of the brain. Nueva York: Vintage.
Felps, W., Mitchell, T., & Byington, E. (2006). How, when, and why bad apples spoil
the barrel: Negative group members and dysfunctional groups. Research in
Organizational Behavior, 27, 175–222.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S0191-3085(06)27005-9
Festinger, L. (1957). A Theory
of cognitive dissonance. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Fleming, P., & Zyglidopoulos, S. (2009). Charting corporate corruption.
Northampton: Edward Elgar Pub.
Geis, G., & Meier, R. (1979). The
white-collar offender. In H. Touch (Ed.), Psychology of crime and criminal
justice. Prospect Heights: Waveland Press.
Giddens, A. (1984). The
constitution of society. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Gigerenzer, G. (2002). Bounded
rationality: The adaptive toolbox. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Goffman, E. (1981). Forms
of talk. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Goffman, E. (1983). La presentación de la persona en
la vida cotidiana. Buenos Aires: Amorrortu.
Haller, D., & Shore,
C. (2005). Corruption. Anthropological perspectives. Londres:
Pluto Press.
Kantorowicz, E. T. (1957). The
king’s two bodies. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Kish-Gephart,
J., Harrison, D., & Trevi ˜no, L. K. (2010). Bad
apples, bad cases, and bad barrels: Metaanalytic
evidence about sources of unethical decisions at work. Journal of Applied
Psychology, 95(1), 1–13. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0017103
Kunda, G. (1992). Engineering culture. Filadelfia: Temple University.
Lehrer, J. (2009). How
we decide. Boston: Mariner Books.
Lerner, J., & Tetlock, P. (1999). Accounting for the effects of
accountability. Psychological Bulletin, 125(2), 255–275.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.125.2.255
Lifton, R. (1986). The Nazi
doctors: Medical killing and the psychology of genocide. Nueva York: Basic.
McLean, B., & Elkind, P. (2004). The smartest guys in the room.
Nueva York: Portfolio Trade.
Messick, D., & Bazerman, M. (1996). Ethical leadership and the psychology
of decision making. Sloan Management Review, 37(2), 9–22.
Milgram, S. (2005). Obedience
to authority. Nueva York: Printer & Martin [1974].
Mols, F., Haslam, A., Jetten,
J., & Steffens, N. (2014). Why a nudge is not enough: A social identity
critique of governance by stealth. European Journal of Political Research,
54(1), 81–98. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1475-6765.12073
Nye, J. (1967).
Corruption and political development: A cost benefit analysis. American
Political Science Review, 61(2), 417–427.
Philp, M. (1997).
Defining political corruption. Political Studies, 45(3), 436–462.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1467-9248.00090
Pinto, J., Leana, C., & Pil, F. (2008).
Corrupt organizations or organizations of corrupt individuals? Two types of
organization-level corruption. Academy of Management Review, 33,
685–709. http://dx.doi.org/10.5465/AMR.2008.32465726
Rest, J. (1986). Moral
development: Advances in research and theory. Nueva York: Praeger.
Rose-Ackerman, S.
(1978). Corruption: A study in political economy. Nueva York: Academic
Press.
Rose-Ackerman, S.
(2014). Corruption and conflict of interests. In J.-B. Auby,
E. Breen, & T. Perroud (Eds.), Corruption and
conflict of interest. A comparative law approach (pp. 3–11). Cheltenham:
Edward Elgar.
Simmel, G. (1906). The
sociology of secrets and of secrets societies. American Journal of Sociology,
11(4), 441–498.
Simon, H. (1947). Administrative
behavior. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Simon, H., Thompson, V.,
& Smithburg, D. (2010). Public administration. Nueva York:
Transaction Publishers [1950].
Sissener, T. (2001). Anthropological
perspectives on corruption. pp. 5. Bergen: Chr. Michelsen
Institute. WP.
Staub, E. (1989). The roots of evil: The
origins of genocide and other group violence. Nueva York: Cambridge
University Press.
Sykes, G., & Matza, D. (1957). Techniques of neutralization: A theory of
delinquency. American Sociological Review, 22, 664–670.
Turse, N. (2013). Killing everything that
moves: The real American war in Vietnam. Nueva York: Picador.
Van Gennep,
A. (1960). The rites of passages. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Weick, K. (2001). Making sense of the
organization. Oxford: Blackwell.
Zerubavel, E. (2006). The
elephant in the room. Silence and denial in everyday life. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Zyglidopoulos, S., & Fleming, P.
(2008). Ethical distance in corrupt firms: How do innocent bystanders become
guilty perpetrators? Journal of Business Ethics, 78(172.), 4–5.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10551-007-9378-4
Zyglidopoulos, S., Fleming, P., &
Rothenberg, S. (2009). Rationalization, overcompensation and the escalation of
corruption in organizations. Journal of Business Ethics, 84(1),
65–73. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10551-008-9685-4
Notes.
1 Andersson and Heywood (2009, p. 749) state that the attempt to
create a global definition of corruption will have to face, no matter what, the
variability of the situations and types of corruption: depending on whether we
are talking about the public or the private sector, of an administrative or
political process; of the actors involved, be they public or private servants,
businessmen, citizens; of the gravity and the scope of the acts (sporadic,
systemic, severe or mere violations). We would add to these variations, those
that are caused by the organizational dynamics that we study in this document.
2 The density of the phenomenon of corruption, seen from
an organizational point of view, makes its understanding even more complex. For
example, it would be necessary to differentiate a corrupt act form other very similar
acts, such as inappropriate behavior (e.g., harassment at the workplace),
deviated organizational behavior (pretending to be working, for example) or
anti-social behavior (e.g. bullying) ( Ackroyd and Thompson, 1999 ). Boundaries are not
rigid, of course, as organizational processes, the three previous behaviors
could lead to a corrupt act. Some authors differentiate it with the obtainment
of a financial gain. This would imply that the organizational corruption of individuals
could go from bribery, financial disguise, over-estimation of expenses or
working hours, fraud, and even robbery. Organizational corruption for the
benefit of the organization would be corporate fraud, business crime and
deviation of the business toward criminal activities.
3 This behavior that appears counterintuitive, has also
been proposed and studied in questions such as evil or outright inhumane acts.
Studies on the Nazi physicians ( Lifton, 1986), the murder of My Lai (Turse, 2013), among others (Staub, 1989 ), have argued that
what is most disconcerting is not finding intrinsically evil beings developing
terrible activities, but rather the opposite: common people trapped in social
and organizational forces.
4 Even making it further from the nudges, which is not
clear, generate a cognitive change ( Mols et al., 2014).
5 One of the most serious obstacles in understanding
corruption most likely has to do with the strength of the moralist and
normative speeches that this concept awakens in contemporary societies. The
concept of contemporary corruption is part of a dominant form of understanding
modern society. On the basis of a definitive and clear separation of the public
from the private, the most accepted concepts of corruption have to do with this
ideal of the separation of two spheres of interests. When the private interest
(legitimate in and of itself) negatively affects the public interest (likewise,
legitimate, though much more abstract and closer to an ideal type), it is then
that the maleficence of corruption appears. The public, pure, is adulterated by
the inadequate interference (it is assumed that there is a possible, adequate
interruption) of the private. This vision, which would be strange in
“pre-modernity”, always implies a normative definition of what makes “pure” the
“public” and what makes said interference of the private, an inadequate
interference. Without the myth and doctrine of “The King's Two Bodies” ( Kantorowicz, 1957 ), these two bodies of
every human being, the concrete and the abstract, the private and the public,
the concept of contemporary corruption is impossible to understand. Part of the
problem is thus in not being aware of the contradictions and limitations of the
somewhat Manichaean vision of human beings in this normative framework,
socially created in reality, from the separation between the public and the
private. This normative and abstract idea, built social and historically (that
of the separation of the public and the private) is, in turn, a political
conceptualization that seeks to impose and normalize certain behaviors and
ideas from a hegemonic framework that tries to establish what is “normal” ( Bratsis, 2003 , p. 17). However, it
is the very illusion of purity of the public and the illusion of auto-control
of the private to respect said purity, what probably makes us lose sight of
just how corruption or the real behaviors of the people dealing with the
artificiality of the spheres of the public and the private, are in themselves
behaviors in social contexts, situations and logics.
Peer review under the responsibility of Universidad
Nacional Autónoma de México.
Copyright © 2017
Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, Facultad de Contaduría y
Administración.
Métricas de artículo
Metrics powered by PLOS ALM
Enlaces refback
- No hay ningún enlace refback.

Este obra está bajo una licencia de Creative Commons Reconocimiento 4.0 Internacional.
CONTADURÍA Y ADMINISTRACIÓN, año 70, 2025, es una publicación trimestral editada por la Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, Colonia Ciudad Universitaria, Delegación Coyoacán, C.P. 04510, México, Ciudad de México, a través de la División de Investigación de la Facultad de Contaduría y Administración - UNAM, Circuito Exterior, s/n, Colonia Ciudad Universitaria, Delegación Coyoacán, C.P. 04510, México, Ciudad de México., Tels. (55) 56 22 84 57, (55) 56 22 84 58 Ext. 144 y (55) 56 22 84 94, http://www.cya.unam.mx, correo electrónico: revista_cya@fca.unam.mx, Editor responsable: José Alberto García Narváez, Reserva de Derechos al Uso Exclusivo No. 04-2016-071316434900-203, otorgada por el Instituto Nacional del Derecho de Autor, ISSN 2448-8410, Responsable de la última actualización de este Número, División de Investigación de la Facultad de Contaduría y Administración-UNAM, José Alberto García Narváez, Circuito Exterior, s/n, Colonia Ciudad Universitaria, Delegación Coyoacán, C.P. 04510, México, Cd., Mx., fecha de última modificación, 29 de enero de 2025.
Las opiniones expresadas por los autores no necesariamente reflejan la postura del editor de la publicación. Se autoriza la reproducción total o parcial de los textos aquí publicados siempre y cuando se cite la fuente completa y la dirección electrónica de la publicación.
Contaduría y Administración by División de Investigación de la Facultad de Contaduría y Administración is licensed under a Creative Commons Reconocimiento- 4.0 Internacional.
Creado a partir de la obra en http://www.cya.unam.mx.
Correo electrónico: revista_cya@fca.unam.mx
ISSN: 0186-1042 (Print) 2448-8410 (Online)